After hearing that Matt Dillahunty was debating Blake
Giunta, I was excited to see a YouTube video
of the debate go up and had it on as background for work this morning.
I happen to like Matt and I actually like when I’ve heard
Blake on various atheist podcasts, like Dogma Debate. He certainly comes off
far better than the majority of popular apologists I’m familiar with.
I was prodded from my Blog/Video slumber to put something up for this debate, so here we go. Let’s start with Blake’s case.
I was prodded from my Blog/Video slumber to put something up for this debate, so here we go. Let’s start with Blake’s case.
Bayes
Blake starts off saying he’s going to use a Bayesian method
to try and argue that belief in a god is more reasonable than not. I’m not
an expert on Bayes, but I do know that this is very likely going to be
moderately useless in this context. A whole lot of the problem with using Bayes for the topic
of “does the god of classical theism exist” is going to boil down very much
into where one starts with subjective prior’s.
There’s a pattern I’ve noticed with people who like to use
Bayesian approaches to argue for or against god’s existence and that they get
to make quite a show of it. They can be “very
generous” in assessing the prior probabilities of their opponents position, but
then will run that position through a gauntlet of things it needs in order to
explain some piece of data, and then due to the multiplication involved, the
number they started with, no matter what it is, will end up extremely low.
This isn’t so much an indictment against Bayes Theorem, it’s
got it’s domain of applicability. It just seems like it can be abused when
applied to grand metaphysical topics, which I’m thinking is just a problem with
grand metaphysical topics in general and not so much Bayes.
My point here is that even if Blake’s arguments work, we can
still acknowledge that he has evidence for god’s existence and still be
atheists, because we can construct our own sets of arguments along the same
lines and then find the balance of the arguments leans towards atheism.
Likewise the theist will end up on theism, and we’re left either arguing about
subjective prior’s or debating which metaphysical view seems more likely for
whatever argument Bayes is being applied to.
Basically, I’m a little skeptical that taking the Bayesian
approach in the context of a debate is going to add much of anything other than letting the presenter make
a show with numbers that favors their side.
Necessity & S5
Modal Logic
Blake mentions S5 and necessary beings, talking about the
intrinsic probability of god before looking at the evidence. Since he’s using a
Bayesian approach, Blake is trying to up the prior probability of god’s existence.
Unlike Matt, I’m generally accepting of S5 modal logic,
though since I’m not an expert on logics in general, that shouldn’t amount to
much of an endorsement. From my
understanding though, it’s generally accepted, though what significance we can
derive from S5 is controversial since it impinges on very contentious topics
like modal realism.
Blake then gives a kind of form of the ontological argument
in that theists understand god to be a necessary being, and if god possibly
exists, then god necessarily exists, ala S5. I have a video on the modal
ontological argument here,
however I wish I had more clearly stated the best objection to the MOA in that
video.
The biggest problem, one that is admitted by Alvin
Plantinga, the originator of the MOA, is that it just as easily proves that the
god of classical theism necessarily does not exist. That is to say that if it’s possible that a
maximally great being does not exist, then it follows that such a being
necessarily doesn’t exist.
Necessity is a funny property in this way. Atheists don’t
have a problem with “necessity”, we have a problem saying the “necessary
something” happens to be the god of classical theism. For theists, “necessary” is just part of the
conjunction of otherwise contingent facts baked into their definition of god as
the greatest possible being (ie. omniscience, omnipotence, omni-benevolence,
etc). The thing is, we can have a “necessary”
something that just doesn’t have the other properties attributed to god defined
as Blake has it.
In fact the most useful definitions of naturalism vs supernaturalism
draws the distinction in this way:
- Naturalism: The necessary something is physical stuff.
- Supernaturalism: The necessary something is mental stuff.
In either case there’s something “necessary” there, and that
“necessary something” is going to have a bunch of contingent qualities that
only become necessary because they’re all sort of joined together by an AND
function.
The Ontological and
Cosmological Arguments have a Kid
From here Blake goes on to make an argument that is like a
combination of the ontological, Kalam, and Leibnitzian cosmological arguments.
It’s actually kind of novel, but it’s going to have some issues.
It hinges on the idea it’s possible that the first contingent
thing is caused to exist. From there
Blake will derive that something necessary must have been the cause and he then
builds on to how it must have been a mind with free will that caused the
contingent thing.
The first problem that leapt at me is that it’s also
possible that the first contingent thing does not have a cause, and exists as a
brute fact – that is something that has no further explanation, but is not
necessary. In fact if we study things
about god, we’ll find that there are number of brute facts built into god’s
necessary nature (ie. that it is loving, etc).
But let’s put all this aside. What I found interesting is how Blake tries to
go from a necessary thing to a personal god:
Blake brings up the question that if the first contingent
thing is caused by a necessary thing, then how is it that the first contingent
thing isn’t itself actually a necessary thing?
His answer is a contra-causal free will, or a libertarian free will. He
then ties the idea of this kind of free will to something that exists only in
persons, and he uses the idea that the big-bang is our “first contingent thing”
to entail that there is a “unembodied person” outside of space and time that
has this kind of causal power.
There are a few rather large problems here. First, the kind
of free will that Blake is discussing, libertarian free will, has no coherent definition
of it in contemporary philosophy. It’s
not defensible, it’s just alluded to as something we should think exists
because of either intuitions or because without it we can’t have moral
responsibility.
Second, there are going to be problems with the idea that
the “first contingent thing”, if caused by a “necessary entity” is itself non-contingent,
if we want to jump from this concept to theism. It’s met with something philosopher
Dan Linford has presented here
as the Cosmological Euthyphro Dilemma:
1.) If God’s reasons for creating the universe came from within Herself, then God did not create the universe of Her free-will. After all, God’s essence is necessarily the way that it is and is unalterable. Thus, any sort of reasons from within God are necessarily the case. God could not have chosen to do otherwise. Worse, not only would God not have free-will, but the universe would not be contingent after all (God exists in every possible world and, since God possesses the same reasons at every possible world, would create the same universe at every possible world — therefore, the universe is not contingent; this contradicts a premise in the argument from contingency).
2.) But now suppose that there were no reasons originating from within God for creating the universe. In this case, there is no where for such reasons to come from. God may have free-will to create the universe, but would be acting arbitrarily and capriciously.
The short of it is that the problem of a “first contingent thing” being caused by a “necessary entity” not ending up itself as a necessary thing is going to be as much of a problem for the theist as it would be for any atheist who thinks there’s some “necessarily existing stuff” like whatever quantum mechanics describes.
Finally, the last problem Blake is going to face is the idea of a non-temporal person. Matt brings up this problem in the debate, and it’s worth going into. This is something I go into some detail on in my last response to William Lane Craig, and it’s also something Dan Linford mentions in his article.
Cosmological Problems
Basically, by tying in the different kinds of cosmological
arguments together into the argument he presented, I believe Blake is just as
susceptible to the standard objections to those arguments as he would be if he
had just presented the classic Kalam or Leibnitzian cosmological argument. Suffice it to say, atheists have quite a few
options open to us in terms of how we think about time and resolve the paradoxes
that come up from there, and our own takes on necessity and contingency that do
not logically entail a god must exist or is more likely to exist.
The Moral Arena
Blake’s next argument is a pretty new one, at least in that
I’ve only seen it in recent years. It’s
the idea that a moral arena existing at all, regardless of whether or not moral
realism is true or not, is evidence that a god exists.
The idea is that if we compare and contrast the ideas of
naturalism vs. theism, on theism we’re going to be assuming some kind of moral agent
already exists. It’s very likely in that if a god was to create beings, they’d
be moral beings. Whereas on naturalism,
there’s just “stuff” that exists, and so we have to run the gamut of getting to
life existing, and then on top of that we need to be able to have the kind of
life that has a complex enough brain to be considered a moral agent.
Here Blake manages to then combine the moral argument into
one with facets of the design argument in order to drive down how unlikely it
is that even life exists.
There are a few responses here.
First and foremost is that we can easily grant that “on
theism” the moral arena is more likely simply because theism assumes a moral
dimension of some kind exists where as “on naturalism” it doesn’t.
However, as Matt alluded to in the debate, Blake has to go
through the same gauntlet of possibilities of embodied agents existing even on
theism. This can be morphed into its own
problem for theism and be evidence for naturalism.
That is the idea that “embodied” agents exist, or that
physical stuff at all exists is actually evidence for naturalism over theism,
in much the same way that the moral arena is evidence for theism over
naturalism.
Blake makes some allusions to the idea that we’d need bodies
in order to maximize our moral agency and development, but this doesn’t make
much sense. God certainly doesn’t need a
body in order to maximize his moral agency, and since when is development even
something to be considered necessary? One must wonder if the angels and demons
(before their fall) had to have bodies, and then does that mean that heaven
exists inside a space-time? Indeed, we
can think of ourselves as purely mental beings that interact with each other directly through some mental substrate and
thus things like mental pain and capacities for sin, etc still exist just as
well as they do in a physical world.
So it’s certainly a bit of a step to say that we should
expect to see physically embodied agents as likely on theism vs. naturalism.
Now what’s worse for Blake’s specific argument is that given
evolution, game theorists have constructed models that show a form of morality
will inherently develop for any kind of biological species that could remotely
be considered a moral agent, if one were to develop.
So at this point Blake’s moral arena argument really does
boil down into a form of the design argument in order to try and hold its
water, and there’s quite a bit to be said against the design argument.
Finally, Blake made a rather outrageous claim about minds
and brains in this argument, basically saying that on atheism we’d think that
brains would work the same regardless of whether or not there’s a “mind” there,
which is just question begging. This is
like taking a hacksaw to the nuanced theories of mind that are available to an
atheist, or just denying superveniance of the mind on the brain.
Final Criticisms of
Blake’s Case
A popular adage is that "The amount of energy necessary
to refute bullshit is an order of magnitude bigger than to produce it."
I’m sure a theist would just as likely level that charge
against atheistic arguments that start simple but have a host of assumptions on
complex and controversial topics. One of
the things I found most annoying about Blake’s case is that he managed to
combine some otherwise distinct arguments and then present us with a chimera of
sorts.
The problem here is that he’s compounding issues in a fairly
complex (though not invalid!) ways that make unpacking them significantly more
complicated in order to try and refute or at least cast doubt on. IMO, this adds yet another order of magnitude
to the atheist’s burden in the debate. Personally I’m shocked at the amount of
digital ink I’ve spilled just partially addressing his arguments.
This certainly seems like a good debate strategy, especially
for popular level debates. To Blake’s
credit, he openly acknowledged that he’s throwing more arguments out than Matt
could possibly hope to respond to in the debate.
Perhaps it’s just an inevitable side effect of these kinds
of debates in general and we end up with the “dueling press conferences” style
of debate. To this organizers credit
they did have a direct interview session, which did somewhat hurt as it was at
the expense of the rebuttal period for either party. However this did force the two to engage
which was exceptionally nice to see, and was a good contrast to the dueling
press conference style that was their opening statements.
What about Matt?
I’m actually in a bit of a flux myself on how I stand on the
issues of naturalism and how a rational person should be approaching these kinds
of metaphysical problems. This ties into
some of the things Matt said in the debate that struck a chord with me.
I noted on Twitter about how I was having some thoughts
about the standard “naturalism vs. theism” kind of dichotomy that is usually
fought over in these debates, and then Matt had endorsed the view that I was
starting to flirt with: the idea that we atheists shouldn’t identify as
naturalists because it goes too far in its claims. This however is a topic far beyond my thoughts
on this debate.
Matt did his usual spiel about how he “finds god not guilty
of existence”, using a courtroom analogy. This is pretty counterintuitive in
how most people look at it, but I actually like the analogy and the way he gets
there.
Matt’s presentation on hiddenness was excellent, I
particularly liked how he points to how god is revealed in the bible and how
that’s somehow no longer done. He also cuts theists off at the pass by pointing
to the supposed existence of Satan as evidence that having direct interaction
with god wouldn’t violate any concepts of free will, even if free will existed
as theists needed it to.
There were a few things Matt said that I take issue with:
- As I alluded to earlier, I’ve no problem with the S5 axiom of modal logic, and there are a variety of ways to get there. The axiom isn’t really controversial so much as what we could really say we are able to derive as metaphysically true from what the axiom would purport to show. This gets into a variety of complex topics in modal realism and semantics of modal logic, etc.
- Matt should have been more careful in how he states the status of arguments for god’s existence are viewed as inconclusive in contemporary philosophy, even by many theistic philosophers of religion. I just don’t think he can be as glib as he was in saying they’re all refuted without presenting arguments.
- Matt needs to be a bit more careful in saying how things must exist in reality as reality is just within space-time. I agree with his points about theists should use different words to describe god since we conceive of persons or minds as necessarily temporal, and we only know of them to be special/embodied. Basically Matt shouldn’t tie “reality” with “within space-time”.
- I think Matt needs to get a bit more up to speed on the demarcation problem for science. Popper style falsification, as wonderfully tempting as it is for us atheists (I’ve succumbed to it to, even on my previous work on this blog), isn’t going to hold up as the ultimate metric in demarking what is and isn’t science. That said, even if science isn’t going to be able to say anything about theism or the supernatural, it doesn’t falsify theism. I think Matt knows this, because he seems to be saying not that theism is necessarily false, but that it doesn’t meet its burden of proof.
Overall, I think Matt did a decent job on presenting good
reasons to doubt the existence of god, and he made some good points with regard
to the counter-intuitive notions theistic morality has about god’s ability to
just kill anyone as he pleases.
If you haven’t already, I recommend watching the debate!
Hey Counter-Apologist, good stuff. I had written something out here in the comments section, but I figured your thoughts were good and deserved to have a blog-post response. So I just put that here: https://beliefmap.org/blog/a-response-to-counter-apologist/
ReplyDeleteThis comment has been removed by the author.
DeleteHello. I'm only commenting because I do identify as a naturalist, and I have no problem saying that. The only thing is, I don't have the philosophical sophistication to defend the view rigorously, so I like to refer people to book written by naturalist philosophers defending that worldview when people ask me why I'm a naturalist.
ReplyDeleteHi all. I spent a day or so working on refuting Giunta's probability calculation. The main mistake he makes, in my opinion, is to pretend that the skeptical position is a single model, rather than a great many possible models. Essentially, he's taken bayesian probability theory, and neglected to sum over all possible models that a skeptical could use.
ReplyDeleteI've written a non-technical essay about this here: http://rationalwiki.org/wiki/Essay:Blake_Giunta_and_the_Butchered_Bayesian
So S5 of modal logic is just a loop-breaker for everlasting loops in (closed) binary systems, like in computer technology. Breaking out of the loop is the 'needed' action to make the program go into a next linear progress (until the next un/in-decisive decision-loop occurs). So, yes, I understand there are necessities derived from possibilities and probabilities in binary logic, but the heavens and the gods of the Olympus (I like the best and want to join in the afterlife) are outside binary logic.
ReplyDelete